Judas
returning the 30 pieces of silver, painting
by Rembrandt, 1629
On
Giving –
and Forgiving
.
by
Hanna-Barbara Gerl-Falkovitz
[Note:
This article is excerpted from a
longer essay, Forgiving
the Unforgiveable? On Guilt and
Pardon, published in (c) Plough
Quarterly Winter 2016 and translated
from German by Peter Mommsen. See full
essay online at Plough.]
Pure Gift: A Prelude to Pure
Forgiveness
In order to understand forgiving,
not least in its biblical depth of meaning,
we must first reflect on giving.
The basis of any economy is exchange – a
fair balance of giving and receiving.
Exchange represents a pragmatic justice that
evens things out. In its drastic form, the
concept of exchange is linked to the rule of
“an eye for an eye, a tooth for a tooth.”
detail of
Rembrandt painting above
Yet where human beings are balanced
against things, where value is balanced
against price, and where life itself is
balanced against money and commodities,
the blurry and debasing nature of
exchange shows up clearly. To take a
well-known example: “And they took the
thirty pieces of silver, the price of
the one on whom a price had been set, on
whom some of the people of Israel had
set a price...” (Matt. 27:9). Thirty
coins are the “balance” that is
exchanged for the Son of Man; when these
coins are thrown back into the temple,
they can just as easily be used to buy a
potter’s field. Exchange breaks down
when things that are unlike are treated
as if they were alike. As this relates
to our topic here: can murder ever be
“balanced out,” or atoned for, or
forgiven – even in exchange for remorse?
The opposite of exchange is the “pure
gift.” Such a gift is supererogatory: it
is above and beyond any price, any
equivalent value, or any debt owed. Such
a gift is gratuitousness itself, it is
pure grace. “If anyone wants to sue you
and take your coat, give your cloak as
well; and if anyone forces you to go one
mile, go also the second mile” (Matt.
5:40–41). A pure gift is not given
according to the logic of the Roman
motto do ut des – “I give that
you might give to me” – but rather in
another sense: “I give because I have
received.” Exact repayment is
transformed into an attitude of free and
unselfish giving-on to others.
The clearest example of this is love.
Love cannot be balanced out through
justice; love exists only when it is not
owed, when it is freely offered. This
pure gift is the heart of creation, and
for Christians, it’s more: it is the
heart of the still greater redemption to
come.
Pure
Forgiveness: A Bridge to the Divine
Taking stock of the horrors of the
twentieth century, Jacques Derrida
(1930–2004) proposed a heightened form of
“pure giving”: he called it
“pure forgiving.” (Derrida plays
on the French terms don pur,
“pure gift,” and pardon pur,
“pure forgiveness.”) He did this expressly
to oppose Jankélévitch’s bitter essay
“Should We Pardon Them?,” arguing against
putting conditions on forgiveness and thus
turning it into a commodity to be
exchanged.
Derrida speaks instead of the
necessity for “pure absolution” from
guilt: absolution as unconditional
forgiveness, offered without receiving
anything in exchange.For-giving
doesn’t depend on balancing guilt with
expiation. That’s why forgiveness
cannot be a provision in criminal law:
it must remain outside of any
balancing of legal rights. After all,
to pardon a criminal means setting
aside the law, and can only ever be
done as an exception; but the act of
pardoning arises from the transcendent
“mystical foundation” of a justice
that legal justice cannot catch up
with.1
Derrida takes aim at Jankélévitch’s
first thesis – that forgiveness may
only be granted (if at all) in a
one-on-one encounter of perpetrator
and victim. If the possibility of
forgiveness really ended with the
death of the victim, then the
perpetrator’s remorse would come too
late; the perpetrator would no longer
have an active role in the drama.
Remorse and forgiveness would then be
logically separated: forgiving
would no longer have a giver,
indeed forgiveness itself would become
mortal. Derrida asks: can forgiveness
really be so time-bound, so finite?
And even more seriously: is
forgiveness then actually something
that is “exchanged” for remorse?
Derrida also detects in
Jankélévitch’s second thesis a
concealed logic of exchange, here in
negative form: for certain crimes such
as crimes against humanity, no
adequate compensation could ever be
offered. What sort of remorse could
ever free a concentration camp
commander from his guilt?
Derrida concludes that it must
bepossible – perhaps it is even
necessary? – to break this cycle of
guilt and expiation. To that end, he
turns to the biblical story of the
original sin: the Bible speaks of the
great sin of Adam and Eve (Gen. 3),
but it speaks too of Yahweh’s a priori
forgiveness, granted already before
the first sin was committed (see Exod.
6–10). Grace is more than a concept, a
speculation, or a wish – grace
“already is.”2
Forgiveness then, according to
Derrida, must extend to forgiving the
unforgivable:
It is
necessary, it seems to me, to
begin from the fact that, yes,
there is the unforgivable. Is this
not, in truth, the only thing to
forgive? The only thing that calls
for forgiveness? If one is only
prepared to forgive what appears
forgivable, what the church calls
“venial sin,” then the very idea
of forgiveness would disappear. If
there is something to forgive, it
would be what in religious
language is called “mortal sin,”
the worst, the unforgivable crime
or harm. ... There is only
forgiveness, if there is any,
where there is the unforgivable.
That is to say that forgiveness
must announce itself as
impossibility itself. It can only
be possible in doing the
impossible. ... What would be a
forgiveness that forgave only the
forgivable?3
In other words: absolution is only
possible in the sphere of the absolute,
not in the relative sphere
of human score-settling. What lies
concealed behind this “absolute”?
Derrida’s argument accords with the
biblical way of thinking: the
Abrahamic faiths all recognize the
possibility of an unimaginable
forgiveness. Indeed, Derrida mentions
the Catholic church, which actually
offers such forgiveness. (Although
Derrida, as a Jew, does not belong to
the church, he is likely thinking of
the Catholic practice of confession.)
Pure forgiveness, in his view, can
only come into being when the
confrontation between two people (even
if both are dead) is resolved through
the presence of Another: a Giver of
forgiveness who is not bound by time.
The dimension of this Other transcends
the realm of human possibilities while
drawing them toward the horizon of
what is impossible, yet nevertheless
imaginable:
Is
forgiveness a matter for human
beings, something belonging to
humankind and within the scope of
human capability – or is it
reserved to God? ... Is it
divine/otherworldly or
this-worldly, consecrated/holy or
not? All debates about forgiveness
have to do with this boundary and
with trespasses of this boundary.4
In contrast to rituals of political
renewal, then, forgiveness involves
something more.
Sending
Guilt Back into Nothingness
Can what has been done be undone through
forgiveness? Certainly, the mystery of
evil cannot be solved by erasing history
(2 Thess. 2:7). Augustine’s insight is
relevant here: according to him, sin
serves to build up a false reality (he
calls it the “privation of good”).
Fundamentally, evil can exercise its
power only by using a stolen mask – it
works only under the false pretense of
being good. The lie consists of
inflating evil, as if it were
something good.
In no way does this deny or
diminish the horrible reality of
guilt or the irretrievable absence
of the victims. Forgiveness means
neither undoing the crime nor
belittling its horror. Face-to-face
with the absolute, something else
happens instead: evil is exposed as
futile, void, nonsensical, even
miserable – and it is then sent back
(remissio) into the
nothingness out of which it emerged.
Evil disappears in the nothingness
of its usurped power, extinguished
in its claim to be “something.” What
does this mean?
Indulgentiam, absolutionem et
remissionem peccatorum nostrorum
– so runs the prayer for forgiveness
in the Roman Mass, which literally
asks for “clemency for, freeing
from, and sending back of
our sins.” Remissio refers
to an objective process: sending
evil back into its nullity,
returning the lie back into its
non-being. Forgiveness directs our
gaze toward the past, but only in
order to allow the past to vanish by
itself into its own nothingness.
Forgiveness takes away from the
past its power to remain present –
to remain in the appalling “eternal
now” of which Jankélévitch speaks.5
Forgiveness frees the present and the
future from the corpse of what has
been.
Forgiveness, then, doesn’t remember
the past in order to keep it
eternally present. Rather, the past
is sent back and vanishes, and
forgiveness forgets it. This is the
sense in which God will, in the
words of Psalm 103, “cast our sins
behind us” – “as far as the morning
is from the evening,” to translate
Jerome’s rendering literally. As the
Psalmist declares:
Bless the Lord
... who forgives all your
iniquity, who heals all your
diseases, who redeems your life
from the Pit, who crowns you with
steadfast love and mercy. ... He
does not deal with us according to
our sins, nor repay us according
to our iniquities. For as the
heavens are high above the earth,
so great is his steadfast love
toward those who fear him; as far
as the east is from the west, so
far he removes our transgressions
from us. As a father has
compassion for his children, so
the Lord has compassion for those
who fear him.
Augustine remarks: “To the
rejected he has promised glory.”6
Echoing this, the sinner can only
say with Kierkegaard: “That you have
forgotten and forgiven, I will
always keep in remembrance.”7
Forgiving thus becomes a gift in an
augmented sense: it means giving
back (remissio) what is
death-bringing into its own
death.
Happy
Guilt?
According to Augustine, the most
elementary meaning of life is summed
up in the phrase videntem
videre – to see the One who has
always seen me. Or in Nicholas of
Cusa’s words: “Your seeing is your
enlivening. ... Your seeing is your
working.”8
God’s gaze and our insatiable
looking back to him are something far
different than our relationship to
anonymous abstractions such as justice
or forgiveness. To see, to let
ourselves be seen, brings a greater
joy than dissolving into a Universal
Everything or Universal Nothing. To
forgive, then, does not mean sinking
back into detachment, but rather it
means entering into a new,
exhilarating relationship: to another
human being, but even more deeply, to
the source of life, to God.
Seen this way, forgiveness is grasped
not as the neutral cancelation of
guilt, but in terms of a Person who is
the source of forgiveness. One pebble
does not forgive another pebble, nor
does the second pebble experience
remorse. To repent and to forgive are
not mechanical processes. They are
acts carried out by persons.
Each year on the night before Easter,
the Exsultet hymn is sung in
churches around the world. This joyous
hymn includes the words of Augustine:
This is
the night that with a pillar of
fire banished the darkness of sin.
This is the night that, even now
throughout the world, sets
Christian believers apart from
worldly vices and from the gloom
of sin ... when Christ broke the
prison bars of death and rose
victorious from the underworld.
Our birth would have been no gain,
had we not been redeemed. ... O
truly necessary sin of Adam,
destroyed completely by the death
of Christ! O happy fault (felix
culpa) that earned for us
so great, so glorious a Redeemer!
... The sanctifying power of this
night dispels wickedness, washes
faults away, restores innocence to
the fallen, and joy to mourners.9
C. S. Lewis once remarked that the
apostle Peter, in his later life,
would likely have told everyone the
story of how he betrayed the Lord –
and done so with a radiant face, since
on that night he had been drawn into
an unimaginable depth of love through
a single glance: “The Lord turned and
looked at Peter. ... And he went out
and wept bitterly” (Luke 22:61–62).
Only in this light can we grasp the
decisive statement: Guilt is only
felt where there is forgiveness.
Normally we think that guilt comes
first, then remorse, then forgiveness.
This reflects ordinary human
experience. But it is not true of God:
it is Jesus’ glance of forgiveness
that prompts the pain of remorse,
which in turn brings about an
awareness of guilt.
In God’s way of redemption, remorse
is not made a condition for “pure
forgiveness.” The “happy fault” not
only dissolves this chain of
connection, but it also puts the
remorseful person’s insight into his
guilt onto a different basis. The
divine goodness that eternally sees
every moment in time has already –
long before there was any guilt –
opened up a place where guilt is
permitted to speak itself out
and be confessed. Confession is
already the first fruit of
forgiveness. The glance of love is
itself the basis on which evil is
repented of. In other words, guilt can
only truly be confessed when it comes
face-to-face with forgiveness.
What is more, when guilt is
confessed, it has already begun to
disappear. One might say that guilt
only becomes evident when it comes
within reach of divine forgiveness.
Only as our burden is being lifted do
we feel its weight.
Divine forgiveness is an
unconditional gift that “overtakes”
remorse. Remorse isn’t what brings on
forgiveness, but the opposite:
forgiveness draws out remorse – not as
a condition for finding
freedom, but as a result of
an overwhelming experience. It is in
this moment that guilt becomes happy,
for it has found its liberator: “Wave
upon wave gushes out of you
inexhaustible, ever-flowing, billows
of water and blood ... rushing over
the deserts of guilt, enriching
overabundantly, overflowing every
heart that receives it, far surpassing
every desire.”10
Notes
Jacques Derrida, “Force of
Law: The Mystical Foundation of
Authority,” in Deconstruction
and the Possibility of Justice,
ed. Drucilla Cornell et al.
(Routledge, 1992), 3–66.
Jacques Derrida,
Pardonner: L’impardonnable et
l’impréscriptible (Galilée,
2005), 70.
Jacques Derrida, “On
Forgiveness,” trans. Michael
Hughes, in On Cosmopolitanism
and Forgiveness (London
& New York: Routledge, 2001),
32–36. See also Derrida, “Das
Jahrhundert der Vergebung:
Verzeihen ohne Macht – unbedingt
und jenseits der Souveränität,”
interview by Michel Wieviorka, in
Lettre international 48
(Spring, 2000): 10–18.
Derrida, Pardonner,
74–75.
Vladimir Jankélévitch,
“Schuld und Vergebung,” in Sinn
und Form: Beiträge zur Literatur
50, no. 3 (1998): 378.
Aurelius Augustinus, Enarratio
in Psalmos, 110 (109), 1.
Søren Kierkegaard,
“Love Hides the Multiplicity of
Sins,” in Taten der Liebe
(1847), GW 19 (1966), 309ff.
Nicholas of Cusa, De
visione Dei 4,13, 5,18, in
Complete Philosophical and
Theological Treatises of
Nicholas of Cusa, trans.
Jasper Hopkins (Arthur J. Banning,
2001), 685–687.
The Roman Missal,
Third Edition (ICEL, 2010).
Hans Urs von
Balthasar, The Heart of the
World, trans. Erasmo S.
Leiva (Ignatius Press, 1979), 153.
Hanna-Barbara Gerl-Falkovitz
is
professor emeritus of philosophy
at Dresden University and head of
EUPHR (European Institute for
Philosophy and Religion) at
Hochschule Heiligenkreuz. Her book
on forgiveness is titled Verzeihung
des Unverzeihlichen? Ausflüge in
Landschaften der Schuld und der
Vergebung (2013)